Towson University
23rd Annual Spring Philosophy Colloquium: Confucius and
Confucianism
The Relation Between Metaphysics and Ethics in Mencius and Plato
presented by Jennifer Leslie Torgerson
April 14, 1999
Table of Contents
1. Introduction
2. Difference one: human essence
3. Difference two: ethics
4. Difference three: ultimate goal of the sage (gentleman,
philosopher)
5. Conclusion
Thesis (three fold)
Many focus upon the similarities
between Mencius and Plato. The purpose
of this paper is to highlight the subtle differences between the two
thinkers. Three main differences
discussed are: (1) the difference in essential human
nature; (2) the difference in ethics;
(3) the difference of the ultimate goal
of the sage (gentleman or philosopher).
Perhaps by seeing that our differences are not that different may enable
an understanding that will encourage individuals to consider their place in the
world, with a truly global perspective.
1. Introduction
Many focus upon the similarities
between Mencius and Plato. The purpose
of this paper is to highlight the subtle differences between the two
thinkers. Three main differences
discussed are: (1) the difference in essential human
nature; (2) the difference in ethics;
(3) the difference of the ultimate goal
of the sage (gentleman or philosopher).
The purpose of understanding human nature is to discover the Way (Tao)
in which to properly conduct one’s life.
The best way is a life of contemplation (the life of the philosopher or
sage). The purpose of looking at the
differences between Mencius and Plato is to also illustrate the so-called
difference between East and West and to demonstrate that these two spheres are
not so far apart. In fact it takes
consideration of the entire world to understand man’s political nature, not
merely one’s country or hemisphere. The
full moon cannot be missing any parts.
Perhaps by seeing that our differences are not that different may enable
an understanding that will encourage individuals to consider their place in the
world, with a truly global perspective.
2. Difference one: human essence
The first difference to be discussed
is the difference between Mencius’ and Plato’s understanding
of human nature. Plato’s view of the
essential human nature is unchanging since human nature is in fact an ideal
form (ideos/edios) that is
separate from the physical body. Mencius
has a view of an original human nature that is capable of change. Mencius also roots this nature (ch’i) in the human heart (hsin),
and hence, such a nature is a part of the physical human existence in that it
dwells within the human body.
“Benevolence (jen) is the heart of man and
rightness is his road. Sad it is indeed
when a man gives up the right road instead of following it and allows his heart
to stray without enough sense to go after it.
[...] The sole concern of learning is to go after this starved heart.”[1] Mencius explains that the original nature of
human essence is that of benevolence. “‘Benevolence’ means ‘man’. When these two are conjoined the result is
‘the Way’ (Tao).”[2]
Benevolence allows man to act
righteously, and find the true path. But
many seem to forget their original nature. “Learn widely and go into what you
have learned in detail so that in the end you can return to the essential.”[3] By returning to our essential original nature
we can be at ease with ourselves knowing the source of benevolence is deep
within ourselves, within our hearts.
There are four incipient tendencies of the heart, of which benevolence
or compassion is only one. The other
three incipient tendencies of the heart are shame, courtesy and modesty, and
right and wrong. “The heart of compassion
is the germ of benevolence; the heart of shame, of dutifulness; the heart of
courtesy and modesty, of observance of the rites; the heart of right and wrong,
of wisdom. Man has these four germs just as he has four limbs.”[4] The most important tendency is that of
benevolence and it is the strongest motive to moral action.
“Why
not go back to fundamentals?”[5] In order to understand the true human essence
one must examine the original nature or what is basic. Mencius contends that the original human
nature or essence is benevolent. “What
is common to all hearts? Reason and rightness.
The sage is simply the man first to discover this common element of my
heart.”[6] This internal nature may not be apparent and
it must be recollected. Such an essence
cannot be discovered a posteriori.
Mencius is skeptical about sensation alone and acknowledges that
benevolence is an intrinsic characteristic of human essence. “The organs of hearing and sight are unable
to think and can be misled by external things.
When one thing acts upon another all it does is to attract it. The organ of the heart (ch’i)
can think. But it will find the answer
only if it does think;
otherwise it will not find the answer.”[7] Mencius describes the nature of the refined ch’i as a rational element, which is immaterial, and is
able to think. It is unlike the body. It is possible to misunderstand the human
essence, especially if one attains to the physical merely.
Mencius
has a special understanding of the heart (ch’i). It is not merely physical since he uses what
is called the flood like ch’i (hao
jan chih
ch’i) which is described as being both the blood and
the heart. It is this ch’i that fills the body (hsueh ch’i). The flood
like ch’i is used by Mencius in place of the physical
ch’i. The
flood like ch’i is more like breath than blood, since
is supposed to fill the body. Mencius
explains this by saying that courage depends on ch’i.[8] When confronted with danger, one’s heart
races, and one begins to breath more heavily, filling
the body. Mencius acknowledges that it
is not easy to explain the flood like ch’i. “This is a ch’i
which is, in the highest degree, vast and unyielding. Nourish it with integrity and place no
obstacle in its path and it will fill the space between Heaven (T’ien) and Earth. It
is a ch’i which unites rightness and the Way.”[9] The flood like ch’i
is Heaven which is planted in the moral heart.
It is only by understanding the flood like ch’i that enables one to act righteously. Benevolence is not part of the physical
existence of our human nature merely, but dwells within the mind, soul, or
heart. By learning to be like the original
nature man will act correctly. Mencius
makes such a quest more attainable than that view of human nature presented by
Plato; since according to Mencius the
root of benevolence, and recollecting our true nature, flows within.
3. Difference two: ethics
Benevolence is the strongest motive to
moral action. To know the good it to do
the good: this is a point where Mencius
and Plato agree for the most part. But their
differing views regarding human essence will result in differing moral
positions. Why do the good? Doing the
good is a matter of self interest according to Plato. Plato claims that the
Ideal Form of the Good is unchanging. He
also claims that virtue has an unchanging essence. Hence, if properly understood, everyone would
know the Good identically, and apply it universally. The difficulty is that the essence of the
Good, and of virtue, are both separate from man.
By rooting right and wrong in benevolence
and rooting benevolence in the flood like ch’i,
Mencius has solved the problem of the chorismos
between matter and form that is present in Plato’s view. Mencius achieves this while also retaining an
original nature which is the ideal man hopes to imitate. “A great man need not keep his word nor does
he necessarily see his action through to the end. He aims only at which is right.”[10] By returning to essentials, or getting back
to basics, man is able to find his true benevolent nature. This exalted nature dwells within every
man.
“All men share the same desire to be
exalted. But as a matter of fact, every
man has in him that which is exalted.
The fact simply never dawned on him.”[11] Men seek the good, but few realize that the
good they seek dwells within. Many think
that good actions are those that produce good consequences, ends, or are
pleasurable, but Mencius explains that right action has nothing to do with
bodily pleasure or good consequences.
Moral action is right action.
Right action is action which is benevolent. When man is benevolent, the result is the
Way.
“A gentleman steeps himself in the Way
because he wishes to find it in himself.
When he finds it in himself, he will be at ease in it; when he is at ease in it, he can draw
deeply upon it, when he can draw deeply upon it, he finds its source wherever
he turns. That is why a gentleman wishes
to find the Way in himself.”[12] The most noted story presented by Mencius
that illustrates that all humans possess an original nature is that of a child
about to fall into a well.[13] Mencius claims that saving the child is not
done because of some dislike of hearing the cries of the child, nor because he
fears what others will think if he fails to act. He rescues the child because he has a heart
of compassion. It is within each man,
and can be drawn upon when needed, since this compassionate nature is part of
the human essence. “Whoever is devoid of
the heart of compassion is not human.”[14] The example of the compassionate man that
acts upon his original benevolent nature is an example of how one should act
benevolently. Mencius thought that right
action could be taught to others, but only those that act to their fullest
potential can be seen as examples of benevolence itself.[15] The cause of being or acting benevolently is
within us.[16]
There are those that seem to not
possess this original nature. Mencius
says that this is like the case of trees and axes.[17] If we were to take axes and lop off a bit of
the trees in our yards, each and every day, it would be no wonder
that the trees would not flourish. It is
the same with man. If a man ignores his
original nature, and does not nourish it, little by little, each and every day,
eventually he “will no longer be able to preserve what was originally in him
and when that happens, the man is not far removed from an animal.”[18] This leads to the mistaken view that such
individuals do not have an original benevolent nature, or that being benevolent
is not part of the essence of man.
Acting benevolently is not only about
being benevolent, it is also about one’s relation to
self and to others. “The way benevolence
pertains to the relation between father and son, duty to the relation between
prince and subject, the rites to the relation between
guest and host, wisdom to the good and wise man, the sage to the Way of Heaven,
is the Decree, but therein also lies human
nature. That is why the gentleman does
not describe it as Decree.”[19] Mencius does not think that benevolence is an universal, or a Decree.
Acting benevolently may mean different things in different
situations. One cannot treat his father
like a stranger. But every son may not
treat his father in the same manner, although each son is to treat his father
with benevolence. The position that
Mencius takes regarding moral matters is sometimes called living the mean
between the extremes. The extremes are
ethical egoism and universal love. Being
extreme may “cripple the Way.”[20] Mencius cautions that the middle path must be
properly measured.[21] How can one measure such a mean? Mencius replies that one “should measure his
own heart.”[22]
Mencius sees his position as the
middle path between egoism and what he calls “love without discrimination.”[23] Ethical egoism is the view that one ought to
act in one’s own self-interest. Mencius
thinks that ethical egoism places too much weight upon pleasures, values, and
consequences. Rightness is not what
brings pleasure, not what is valued, nor what produces favorable
consequences. The right way is the way
which is benevolent. Benevolence may be
valued, but its being valued does not make it
benevolent, it is benevolent in and of itself.
Mencius does not want to advocate that pleasurable activities are
benevolent, due to their pleasure merely, since this may led to
indulgence. It is also the case that
doing the right thing may be difficult, and not necessarily be that action
which produces the most pleasure.
Mencius says: “think of the consequences before you speak of the short
comings of others.”[24] Hence he is not saying that the consequences
of action do not matter, he is advocating the view that the consequences cannot
be the measure merely. The consequences
or the end result may not be known prior to completion of the action. An action that was deemed to produce
favorable consequences may be over-rated.
Also the means may not be benevolent, even if the end result may
be. The main difficulty with
teleological ethics is that such ethical theories claim that right action is
action that produces pleasurable results.
The good cannot be what is merely desired. The good is not a result of, or determined
by, consequences.
“Benevolence is like archery: an archer makes sure his stance is correct
before letting fly the arrow, and if he fails to hit the mark, he does not hold
it against his victor. He simply seeks
the cause within himself.”[25] Mencius uses this metaphor several times to
explain the nature of the middle path.
It may take practice and aim, but eventually one will hit the target. If one fails to meet the target, the cause is
within himself.
He must seek to understand the benevolence that dwells within. “A gentleman is full of eagerness when he has
drawn his bow, but before he lets fly the arrow, he stands in the middle of the
path, and those who are able to do so follow him.”[26] Hence the sage must set the example. Because
it is not always clear to all what acting benevolently is, it is up to the sage
to teach by example. Benevolence is
taught to others by means of benevolence itself.[27]
But why is not the middle path a type
of “love without discrimination”? Love
without discrimination is also called universal love. This is the position that one ought to treat others
the way in which one wants to be treated at all times. Love without discrimination can be seen as
the middle path between ethical egoism (to love self) and ethical altruism (to
love others). But universal love (to
love self and others) is only an apparent mean.
Mencius claims that when properly measured, the proper ethical mean will
be between that ethical egoism and universal love, and this mean is called
graduated love. Graduated love is that
view that one may love some more than others.
Due to the fact that it is not a Decree, the view of Mencius cannot be
seen as a type of universalism, and Mencius is too against a total
altruism. Mencius says: “Try your best to treat others as you would
wish to be treated yourself, and you will find that this is the shortest way to
benevolence.”[28] He also says that “you can only try your best
to do the good.”[29] Although a son should never skimp expenditure
upon his parent’s funeral expenses, it may not be possible to provide the
finest woods, due to economic circumstances, but a gentleman tries to show his
filial piety the best he can.[30] Notice that Mencius says “try”. This is not a categorical imperative that we
ought to always treat others the way we wish to be treated. Mencius is not making this an
universal Decree, but is merely using it as an example. If one is not clear on what benevolence
itself is, then by all means acting in accordance with the “Golden Rule” is better than
acting egoistically. The problem with
following the Golden Rule is that it pretends to be a Decree that is inflexible; furthermore, the
Golden Rule is based upon desire. It is
in one’s interest to treat others as they would be treated. Benevolence cannot be based on such desires
or wishes. The most difficult problem
with the Golden Rule is that it ignores the fact that benevolence is about
relation in its universal application.
“There are no young children who do not know loving their parents, and none of them when they grow up will not know respecting their elder
brothers. Loving one’s parents is
benevolence;
respecting one’s elders is rightness. What is left to be done is simply the
extension of these to the entire Empire.” [31] Correct action flows from benevolence. By understanding love, man will learn respect
for others. One cannot love all
individuals alike. Hence one cannot love
one’s father in the same way he loves his brother. One cannot love his brother in the same way
in which he loves his neighbor. He
cannot love his neighbor in the same way he loves a stranger. Loving one’s parents is good. Respecting one’s parents is the right thing
to do. “Benevolence is the heart of man, and rightness is his road.”[32] Now the task is apply these principles to the
entire state.
4.
DIFFERENCE THREE: ULTIMATE GOAL
OF THE SAGE (GENTLEMAN, OR PHILOSOPHER)
“A gentleman is sparing with things
but shows benevolence towards them; he shows benevolence towards the people but
is not attached to them. He is attached
to his parents, but is merely benevolent towards the people, he is benevolent
towards the people, but is merely sparing with things.”[33] We are frugal with our love, and we do not
just love anything or anyone.[34] In fact, love is only to be applied to
relations we have with others and not to things. A ruler is in a special position in that he
must love his people, but not in the manner in which he loves his parents. He will be forever attached to his parents
and they deserve a certain amount of respect and love beyond all others. The ruler must love his people, but he is not
bound to them. This means that the ruler
may not act the same towards everyone in the Empire. A wise ruler knows that
some things require more attention or more love than others. “A wise man knows everything, but he
considers urgent only that which demands attention. A benevolent man loves everyone but he
devotes himself to the close association with good and wise men.”[35] We should be frugal with our love, but most
of all, of this, the ruler must be aware.
If the ruler was to treat everyone in the same way, either by loving all,
or by being self interested,
neither way would result in the true path.
According to both Mencius and Plato,
states are best run by those who understand the essence of the Good. Both Mencius and Plato think that the essence
of human nature is good, or that to know the good is to do the good. They did not agree, however, about the
location of this human essence. Mencius
thinks that human essence is immanent within each
human, while Plato thinks that humans merely imitate the ideal essence of humanness,
which is separate from all humanity.
Plato’s idea of the Good also exists separate from the essence of
humanness, unlike Mencius’ view of intrinsic human essence which dwells in each
man. Mencius opts for a graduated view
of ethics, since he thinks that to take the mean is the right path between the
extremes. Doing the good, or taking the
right path, is not done because it is in one’s self interest. In Plato’s view, doing the good was a matter
of self interest, and applied universally.
Mencius’ conception of a changing human nature affects his conception of
the good. These differences,
too result in differing views of state.
Plato thinks that those who best
understand the essential form of the Good, the essential form of courage,
justice, temperance, and all other virtues, should be our rulers. Such individuals are at times called
philosopher-kings. Plato believes that
these individuals are the only individuals that can be trusted with the public
good. But might not the role of being
ruler be a type of corruption? The ruler
needs an objective, benevolent advisor to help him discern the middle path
between individual and collective interests.
Being at the most respected position of society may make the ruler, in
thinking he should be treated most benevolently, make
decisions that cripple the Way.
The true role of the sage, gentleman,
or philosopher is not to be the philosopher-king, as Plato suggests. According to Mencius, the true role of the
sage is to help the king rule benevolently.[36] “A benevolent man would not even take from
one man to give to another, let alone seek territory at the cost of human
lives. In serving his lord, a gentleman
has only one aim and that is to put him on the right path and set his mind on
benevolence.”[37] The king should act in what Mencius calls the
Kingly Way, but
this by no means means that all wise men should be
kings.[38] “A gentleman delights in three things, and
being ruler over the Empire is not amongst them.”[39]
5.
CONCLUSION
The paper examined three basic
differences: (1) the
difference in essential human nature; (2)
the difference in ethics; (3) the
difference of the ultimate goal of the sage (gentleman or philosopher). Plato argued for an unchanging human essence
that was separate from man, while Mencius argued for an original, changing
human nature that dwelled within each individual. Plato argued that to know the good was to do
the good. Goodness for Plato was an universal. Plato
held that everyone would find it in their self interest to do the good. Plato held that the best rulers are
philosophers, since they best understand benevolence. Mencius also held that to know the good is to
do the good. For Mencius, goodness was
not an universal, since it was not right to apply
benevolence to everyone equally. Mencius
thought that kings should be benevolent and wise, but that philosophers should
not be kings.
This paper examined the subtle
differences between the views of Mencius and Plato, as an illustration of the
difference between East and West. There
may be many cultural differences, but in fact, we all share the same human
essence. This is evident by examination
of the philosophical traditions of East and West. Philosophers in both East and West have
similar concerns about human existence.
Mencius says[40]: “There is no greater joy for me to find, on
self-examination, that I am true to myself.”
This is similar to the decree over the Delphic Oracle “Know Thyself”. It also reminds me of that famous line of
Socrates that the “unexamined life is not worth living.”[41] The only way to be true to thyself
is to know one’s self. The only way to
know one’s self is to examine one’s heart.
When one finds his benevolent nature, the result is the Way.
Typically, Eastern philosophy and Western
philosophy are seen as oppositional, but this is not actually the case. There are differences, but philosophy, as a
discipline, appears to have particular elements which transcend cultures. A case in point is the comparison of Mencius
and Plato. Although, prima facie,
Shantung and Athens are worlds apart, this is not actually the case. The nature of the sage is the same for both
Mencius and Plato, in that the purpose of philosophizing is to better understand
human nature so that a theory of ethics and state can be developed which best
suits human nature. In philosophy it
seems the moon is full.
[1] Mencius, translated by D.C. Lau, (New York: Penguin Books, 1970), page 167. Book VI, A, 2.
[2] Mencius, page 197. Book VII, B, 16. (This citation contained a typo
in my original paper)
[3] Mencius, page 130. Book IV, B, 15.
[4] Mencius, pages 82-83. Book II, A, 6.
[5] Mencius, page 50. Book I, A, 7.
[6] Mencius, page 164. Book VI, A, 7.
[7] Mencius, page 168. Book VI, A, 15.
[8] Mencius, page 25.
[9] Mencius, page 77. Book II, A, 2.
[10] Mencius, page 130. Book IV, B, 11.
[11] Mencius, page 169. Book VI, A, 17.
[12] Mencius, page 130. Book IV, B, 14.
[13] Mencius, page 82. Book II, A, 6.
[14] Mencius, page 82. Book II, A, 6.
[15] Mencius, page 170. Book VI, B, 20. Also see page 83, Book II, A, 7.
[16] Mencius, page 83. Book II, A, 7.
[17] Mencius, page 165. Book VI, A, 8.
[18] Mencius, page 165. Book VI, A, 8.
[19]
Mencius, page 199. Book VII, B,
24. Also see page 90 and page 187.
[20] Mencius, page 188. Book VII, A, 26.
[21] Mencius, page 188. Book VII, A, 26.
[22] Mencius, page 57. Book I, A, 6.
[23] Mencius, page 188. Book VII, A, 26.
[24] Mencius, page 129. Book IV, B, 9.
[25] Mencius, page 83. Book II, A, 7.
[26] Mencius, page 192. Book VII, A, 41. “When the prince is
benevolent, everyone else is benevolent [...].” Mencius, page 129. Book IV, B,
5.
[27] Mencius, page 170. Book VI, A, 20.
[28] Mencius, page 182. Book VII, A, 4.
[29] Mencius, page 71. Book I, B, 14.
[30] Mencius, page 90. Book II, B, 7.
[31] Mencius, page 184. Book VII, A, 15.
[32] Mencius, page 167. Book VI, A, 11.
[33] Mencius, page 192. Book VII, A, 45.
[34]
Mencius is making a play upon the word “ai” in
Chinese which means both “to love” and “to be sparing, to be frugal”. Mencius,
page 192.
[35] Mencius, page 192. Book VII, A, 46.
[36] Mencius, page 53. Book I, A, 5.
[37] Mencius, page 178. Book VI, B, 8.
[38] Mencius, page 51. Book I, A, 3.
[39] Mencius, page 185. Book VII, A, 20. “His parents are alive and his brothers are
well. This is the first delight. Above, he is not ashamed to face Heaven;
below he is not afraid to face man. This
is the second delight. He has the good
fortune of having the most talented pupils in the Empire. This is the third delight.”
[40] Mencius, page 182. Book VII, A, 4.
[41] Apology, 38, A.