CHAPTER 2

 

QUINE ON ONtolOGY

 

                                   

            This chapter will examine four ontological topics.  First to be examined is Quine’s distinction between meaning and naming, followed by a discusion of the differences between realism, conceptualism, and formalism.  The third topic examined is the distinction between phenomenalism and physicalism.  The fourth section briefly examines four kinds of nominalism:  predicate, concept, class, and resemblance. 

 

            In his essay, “On What There Is”, Quine begins by establishing a list of things which do not grant the existence of an universal concept.  First singular terms can be used without entailing the existence of an entity named.  Second, general terms or descriptions can be used without entailing that these words refer to abstract entities.  Third, claims of synonymy can be made without the entailment of some realm of meaning.  Quine does not use empirical evidence to develop his categories; they seem to come to him innately.  Quine also discussed the limit to the range of a bound variable, and concedes that to be is not to be the value of a bound variable.[15] He also described realism, conceptualism, and formalism in terms of what each would permit a bound variable to range over, and Quine found nominalism to be the most suitable of the ontological views, yet he did not discuss this view, but he employed it implicitly.  He then explains the difference between phenomenalistic conceptual schemes and physicalistic conceptual schemes, seeming to favor physicalistic schemes over phenomenological ones, but in the end of this essay claims that the phenomenological conceptual scheme takes epistemological priority. [16]  Quine does abandon phenomenalism by the time of Word and Object in 1960.

 

 

Ontology is the study of being, or what it means to be.  Ontology is a study of essence, not existence. An important issue in the study of ontology is whether or not universals exist.  Quine addresses this issue in “On What There Is”. He begins by asking the basic ontological question “What is there”? [17]  Quine argues that no one would disagree that the answer to the question is “everything,” but this a vague answer.[18]  What is this everything that is?  If two people disagree on an ontological issue one would have to affirm that something is the case, while the other denies that something is the case.  “It would appear that in any ontological dispute the proponent of the negative side suffers the disadvantage of not being able to admit that his opponent disagrees with him.” [19]  This forces the proponent of the negative side to posit that which the proponent claims does not exist as that which is not. Quine goes on to mention that this is the old dilemma created by Plato of non-being.  According to Quine, there must be something which is non-being, or something which is not in contrast to that which is.[20] This leads philosophers to “mistaken” points of view, that even Pegasus exists, or to “impute being where they might otherwise be quite content to recognize that there is nothing.”[21]  Because we know that a being must be a certain kind, it does not follow that there needs be an existing being of that kind.  Quine is correct in making his distinction between actual and imaginary, but in doing so, he is not shifting the discussion towards existence. He is not concerned with there being an actual object existing, but merely a possible object.  An object is a thing of a certain kind if there is a being that has such and such attributes, but there need not be any such object.  

 

            The epistemological distinction between concept and object, when the referent is actual, is clear.  Yet in the case of concepts which do not refer to actual objects, such as Pegasus, Quine argues that it is necessary to say that there is something which is not.  In order to escape this dilemma, and to separate himself from realistic philosophers, Quine uses the copula ‘is’ without the existence predication.[22] Quine echoes Kant’s criticism, of the ontological argument, as applied to the existence of God, that existence is not a real predicate.[23]  Hence Quine has concluded that using terms like “Pegasus” does not in fact presuppose an existent being that is being named by that term.  “Russell, in his theory of so-called singular descriptions, showed clearly how we might meaningfully use seeming names without supposing that there be entities allegedly named.”[24] Quine calls these “so-called singular descriptions” because such descriptions usually are phrases which describe, and not singular terms.

            [T]he burden of objective reference which had been put upon the descriptive phrase is now taken over by words of the kind logicians call bound variables, variables of quanification namely, words like ‘something’, ‘nothing’, ‘everything’. [...] These quantificational words or bound variables are, of course a basic part of  language, and their meaningfulness, at least in context, is not to be challenged.[25]

 

Bound variables now replace descriptive phrases, and are functional because they are more general.  Hence we can use more general terms, and they as well as other terms, need not imply the existence some entity.

 

            So it can be said that “the round square cupola on Berkeley College is not” is a descriptive phrase that does not refer to some actual entity.[26]  “Now what of ‘Pegasus’? This being a word rather than a descriptive phrase, Russell’s argument does not immediately apply to it.”[27]  All we have to do, Quine continues, is to substitute a phrase for the singular term, that is synonymous with the singular term.  The singular term must be translated into a description.[28]  Russell had come up with a solution to Plato’s paradox with his theory of descriptions, and Quine acknowledges his acceptance of it as well.[29]  Quine states in Word and Object:  

            It is the difference, so central to Russell’s philosophy, between description and acquaintance.  It is kept before us in synchronic behavior as a difference between the non-observable occasion sentences, with their random variation in      stimulus from speaker to speaker, and observational sentences with their socially `uniform stimulus meanings. [30]

 

What if the singular term was an obscure term?  Would a description like “the thing that is-Pegasus” lead to the contention that universals exist? Quine thinks not.  “If in terms of pegasizing we can interpret the noun ‘Pegasus’ as a description subject to Russell’s theory of descriptions, then we have disposed of the old notion that Pegasus cannot be said not to be without presupposing that in some sense Pegasus is.” [31]  Quine has stated that descriptions for singular terms do not imply that there is a being to which the description refers in existence.

 

            Quine describes the accepting of the existence of entities in “Plato’s heaven” as non sequitur, and that he is not interested in non-being or being of universals.[32] To posit universals would be to create a bloated universe as far as Quine is concerned.[33]

 

 

MEANING AND NAMING

 

            The existence of universals, or the existence of attributes or categories based on like objects all having something in common, is merely trivially true for Quine.[34]  He notes that one’s ontology is fundamental to formulating an epistemology or ‘conceptual scheme’.[35] Unfortunately, Quine does not define ‘conceptual scheme’.[36]  Ontological statements need no justification because they are basic and important for understanding our conceptual schemes.  “One’s ontology is basic to the conceptual scheme by which he interprets all experiences, even the most commonplace ones.  Judged within some particular conceptual scheme -- and how else is judgment possible? -- an ontological statement goes without saying, standing in need of no separate justification at all.”[37]

In “Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis” Quine describes his pragmatic approach to ontology as a type of ontological relativism.  “Concepts are language, and the purpose of language, and the purpose of concepts and of language is efficacy in communication and in predication.  Such is the ultimate duty of language, science, and philosophy, and it is in relation to that duty that a conceptual scheme has finally to be appraised.”[38]  When a conceptual scheme that multiplies entities beyond necessity to use Ockham’s razor, or is “too unwidely for our poor minds to cope with effectively” in Quine’ terms, then “elegance is simply a means to the end of a pragmatically acceptable conceptual scheme.  But elegance also enters as an end in itself -- and quite properly so as long as it remains secondary in another respect; namely, as long as it is appealed to only in choices where the pragmatic standard prescribes no contrary decision.  Where elegance doesn’t matter, we may and shall, as poet, pursue elegance for elegance’s sake.”[39]  Simplicity and elegance as means to an end echoes Kant once again.  Quine states how we must see ontology as basic to conceptual schemes, and all judging is from within such a scheme. 

 

            He also notes the difference between meaning and naming.[40]  Meaning is conceptual, or mind dependent.  Meanings explain what a thing would need to be if it were of the kind in question.  It does not, he contends, imply that there is a named or actual entity that exhibits theses qualities.[41]  Quine claims that it is the confusion of meaning with naming which induces philosophers to acknowledge the existence of universals. He is also claiming that it is this confusion of between meaning and naming that leads to belief in universal concepts.

            There is a gulf between meaning and naming even in the case of a singular term,    which is genuinely a name of an object. The following example from Frege will serve.  The phrase “Evening Star” names a certain large physical object of          spherical form, which is hurling through space some scores of millions of miles       from here.  The phrase “Morning Star” names the same thing[.] [...] But the two phrases cannot be regarded as having the same meaning[.] The meaning, then,            being different from one another, must be other than the named object, which is one in the same in both cases.[42]

 

 

Those that hold that universals exist have confused meaning with the named object, according to Quine, and what they have mistakenly called universals are actually attributes. Just because there are red houses and red sunsets, Quine in no way thinks that this leads to the affirmation of the existence of red-ness.  The way he avoids the universal is to reject meaning, or the intensional meaning. Quine seems to only be rejecting intensional meaning, since he thinks there a confusion between meaning and naming.[43]  “[T]he only way I know how to counter it is by refusing to admit meaning.”[44]  It does not follow that Quine thinks that words and statements are not meaningful.  Quine considers the reliance upon definitions to convey meaning is a reliance upon an illusion.[45]  Does one have to admit to the existence of universals merely because some meanings are synonymous?  Quine offers, of course, the negative answer to this question.

 

            Quine has not abandoned meaning.  He wants to ensure that the confusion between meaning and naming will be eliminated, and this can be accomplished if meaning is restricted to extensional meaning.  Intensional meaning is the set of characteristics a thing must have to be named the thing that it is.  In contrast, extensional meaning is the set of things to which the definition applies, and involves the naming of things that fit the meaning or characteristics of the class (class concepts). He wants to ban intensional objects by using extension instead.[46]

 

           

 

            Quine is not referring to actual, physical entities with his naming.  He is referring to variables.  Ontological committal descriptions are the kind to which Quine wants to apply his bound variables.  Quine contends that names are easily converted into descriptions, but what of the bound variable? [47]  Quine says that the use of the bound variable is the only situation in which ontological commitments are involved.[48] We could change the name, or eliminate them all together:  “To be assumed as an entity is, purely and simply, to be reckoned as the value of a variable.”[49]  This answers the question of being: “that to be is to be in the range of reference of a pronoun.”[50] He will say a few pages later:  “To be is be the value of a variable.”  This results in an indeterminacy of translation.  There are no such things as non-relative facts.  Quine contends  that use of bound variables in ontology will not explain what there is, but about what one believes to be what is.  Perhaps all we can know is our beliefs about what that object or other is, but not the this (or its essence). This is not a claim about existence, but about language and belief. 

 

             Objective truth is not possible given Quine’s usage of ontological relativity.  Variables are bound in the scope of a quantifier.  Statement functions use bound quantifiers;  such statements have variables that are all abound within the scope of the same quantifier. [51]  Quine defines pronoun as “the basic media of reference.”[52] Bound variables like ‘something’, ‘nothing’, ‘everything’ are included in ontologies, and the existence of such ranging variables does not necessary imply the existence of the entities being described.  Quine believes that:  “[W]e are convicted of a particular ontological presupposition if, and only if, the alleged presupposition has to be reckoned among the entities over which our variables range in order to render one of our affirmations true.”[53] Quine offers an example to illustrate his point  To accept the presupposition ‘Some dogs are white’ is true there has to be at least some actual dogs that are in fact white, hence the bound variable ‘something’ ranges over actual entities if this is the case.  This bound variable, or the use of the existential quantifier, in no way forces him to accept or admit that there is some entity of ‘whiteness’ or dogness, Quine contends. Only if there are some white dogs, the presupposition ‘Some dogs are white’ is true.  He in no way wished to commit to the existence or being of abstract entities.

 

 

 

REALISM, CONCEPTUALISM, AND FORMALISM

 

            Quine believes we now have a clear standard to determine the truth of presuppositions, or “an implicit standard whereby to decide what ontology a given theory or form of discourse is committed to:  a theory is committed to those and only those entities to which the bound variables of the theory must be capable of referring in order that the affirmation made in the theory be true.” [54]  This brings Quine to the descriptions of possible ontological theories, or “points of view” that had been debated in medieval philosophy and were now entering into discussions among modern mathematicians.[55] The debate among the modern mathematicians, Quine relates, is this: to what extent do the bound variables actually range over entities, or what range of entities is acceptable for bound variable reference? [56]

 

            Quine defines realism, conceptualism, and formalism to illustrate their similarity with modern mathematical positions of logicism, intuitionism, and formalism for various answers to the question of the reference of bound variables. [57]  Realism is, according to Quine:  “the Platonic doctrine that universals or abstract entities have being independently of the mind; the mind may discover them but cannot create them.”[58]  Realism as conceived by Aristotle still maintained that we could only know our perceptions of the world, and not the independent objects (composite of matter and form or hylomporphic composition) existing in the natural world as they truly are.  Plato, an idealist, made the knowledge of essence even more difficult by separating matter from essence (or form).[59]  This is mirrored in the Logicism of Frege, Russell, Whitehead, Church, and Carnap.[60] 

            “Logicism [is t]he view pioneered by Frege and Russell, that received mathematics, in particular arithmetic, is part of logic.  The aim was to provide a system of  primitives and axioms (which on interpretation yielded logical truths) such that all arithmetical notions were definable in the system and all theorems of arithmetic were theorems of the system.  If successful, the program would ensure that our knowledge of mathematical truths was of the same status as logical truths.”[61]

 

He claims that Ockham, a medieval nominalist, had his razor dulled by cutting through the unnecessary entities of Plato’s universe.[62]  A nominalist is one that denies the existence of forms or universals. Nominalists call forms as merely names; universals are only to be found in predicatations in our language-making  Nominalism is the view that universals do not have an independent existence but are merely names.[63]  Quine is a nominalist. Quine makes no secret of his disagreement with Plato.[64]  Plato accepted the existence of universals separate from the things of the sensible world.  Of course, this is what Quine is denying.  As realist, Aristotle, differed on the “location” of the universals, claiming that to be known the forms must be immanent in the matter of which they are forms, or hylomorphic composition.  Universals are abstracted from particulars. Nonetheless, this is still an affirmation of a class or group of essential entities, separate from the mind, and hence, realism. The logicians accept “the use of bound variables to refer to abstract entities known and unknown, specifiable and unspecifiable, indiscriminately.”[65] Quine will not tolerate this use of bound variables ranging over possible instead of actual entities.  The entities must be known to determine whether the bound variables accurately range over them.  Being known and determinate is not just a mere concept but a reference to something real known by our senses.  This kind of reference or verification cannot be done with abstract entities, especially unknown entities of any kind.  An example of such a mathematical abstract entity is n + 1.  The natural number series could not continue without the potentiality of n + 1 (in example 1 + 1 = 2; 2 + 1 = 3; 3 + 1...) There cannot be 2 without 1.  The existence of such a continual series is not known a posteriori, but only a priori, and is a mathematical concept. But is there a concept of 1 which itself exists?  Do universals exist as separate entities?    Quine does not think that universal or abstract terms have an existence. 

 

            Conceptualism is, according to Quine, the view that “there are universals but they are mind made.”[66] “Conceptualism [is t]he theory of universals according to which general or abstract terms (such as ‘substance’ or ‘humanity’) have meaning because they name or otherwise refer to corresponding non-physical entities, called concepts.  In the most substantial, and perhaps least plausible view, these concepts are taken to be mental images.”[67]  According to Quine, sense experience and language are interwoven and cannot be separated from each other.  Language is an expression of thoughts in the “mind”.  The mind is not a collection of separate things, each with its separate empirical definition.[68] There is not a separate mind, according to Quine, where thoughts, in any form, exist independent from experience.  Nor can experience exist independent of what is thought about it. 

 

            Conceptualism is in opposition to realism because the conceptualists hold that universals or concepts are mind made, while the realists do not think that universals are mind made, or mind dependent, since universals are abstracted from the Forms that are present in the objects in Aristotle’s view.  Intuitionism is the modern view similar to Conceptualism. Of their range of acceptance of bound variables referring to abstract objects Quine states: “only when those entities are capable of being cooked up individually from the ingredients specified in advance.”[69]

 

            Intuitionism [is a] system produced by Brouwer, identifying truth with being known to be true, that is, proven.  The main theses of intuitionism are:  that a mathematical entity exists only if a constructive existence proof can be given; and that a (mathematical) statement is true only if there is proof of it, and false only if a proof of its denial can be given.  Brouwer’s idealist inclinations led him to describe      mathematics as investigation of the (ideal) mathematician’s “mental constructions”.       

The view is notable for its rejection of classical logic, and in particular  the law of double negation, the law of the excluded middle,

and the classical reductio [ad absurdum].[70]

 

 

The opposition between realists and conceptionalists is not a mere “quibble”.  The position one takes will influence one’s view of mathematics and in particular one’s view of the levels of infinity.[71]  Realists have orders of infinity that are ascending, while conceptualists do not go beyond the first level of infinity, or lowest order of infinity, and in effect abandon classical mathematical laws regarding real numbers.[72]

 

            Formalism is, according to Quine,  the unbridled recourse to universals.” [73]  The Formalists are much like nominalists, in that they do not admit to the existence of universals in the way that realists and even the conceptualists do, but nonetheless cling to them for safety.  We need not throw out mathematical principles like the conceptualists, but the formalists admit to the existence of abstract entities, and this is something conceptualists do not recognize.  The rules that govern mathematical systems need only be examined and this can serve as an adequate basis of agreement among individuals of any ontological following:  “[T]hese syntactical rules being, unlike the notions themselves, quite significant and intelligible.” [74] From this statement, Quine attempts to find a suitable ontology among the options, but he asks:  “[H]ow are we to adjudicate among rival ontologies?” [75] Perhaps we need not abandon all elements of an old theory of ontology to establish a new one, “[i]f the new theory can be so fashioned as to diverge from the old only in ways that are undetectable in the most ordinary circumstances, then it inherits the evidence of the old theory rather than having to overcome it.  Such is the force of conservatism even in the context of revolution.”[76]  It cannot be accomplished by using “To be is the value of a variable”, a mere semantic formula. [77] Quine notes that we are not trying to discover what there is, but what someone else says there is. [78]  Hence, according to Quine, we can only know our beliefs about the world, and not the world in and of itself.  Our beliefs about the world are changing.  The web of beliefs is constantly being examined and reexamined.  When it is discovered that a belief no longer suits our uses, it is changed or discarded.  Things cannot be known in and of themselves;  all we know are the predicates in our language-making.   Hence the only possible ontology is ontological relativism.  We cannot look merely to the bound variable to find the ontological standard, since the bound variables must be verified to actually range over the entities they bound over, in conformity to a pre-existing ontological standard. [79] This has been a semantical discussion in the debate over what there is; there was the predicament of not being able to admit that there are disagreements, and the side of the opponent was disadvantaged.  Quine hopes that the collapse or reduction of this debate into a debate over words may eliminate any question-begging. [80]  Is this a mere debate of words?  It seems the reliance upon an empirical sense field theory from which our perceptions of the world are obtained ensures such a relativity.  This kind of relativity leads to the inability to hold one theory as better at explaining the nature of reality than another -- there could always be another paradigm shift.  Ontological relativity would, Quine hoped, end mere quibbles over words, but it has not. This reminds me of a passage in Through the Looking-Glass where Alice is told by Humpty Dumpty, after a discussion of un-birthday presents that are given 364 days a year opposed to once a year for birthday presents, “there’s glory for you!”.[81]  Alice replies that she is not sure what he means by glory.  “Of course you don’t-- till I tell you.  I meant ‘there is a nice knock-down argument for you!’” Humpty Dumpty retorts.

            But glory does not mean ‘a nice knock down argument’,” Alice objected. “When I use a word,” Humpty Dumpty said, in a rather scornful tone, “it means just what I choose it to mean--neither more or less.” “The question is,” said Alice, “whether you can make words mean so many different things.” “The question is,” said Humpty Dumpty, “which is to be the master--- that’s all.[82]

 

Hence if such ontological relativity is permitted, words can mean just about anything an individual likes.  If this is the case, Philosophy has not progressed beyond the ideology of Protagoras and his homo mensura.  Too bad the king did not really mean that all his horses and all his men could really put Humpty Dumpty back together again.  Therein lies the problem.  If ontology, and thus meaning of words can be relative, no one will be sure of what anyone else is really trying to express anymore.  Hence, Quine attempts to ground his relativity with the physical sciences.  Due to the fact that the physical sciences are themselves in a state of constant change, and revision, constantly shifting meanings within its theoretical statement making.  Quine has tried to ground the relative in the relative.  In Quine's view, we should be the master of words in our conception-making.  Thus, we should only agree to those concepts that fit into a set of true beliefs about the world, supposedly gained from mere sense stimuli:

            Our acceptance of an ontology is, I think, similar in principle to our acceptance of a scientific theory, say a system of physics:  we adopt, as least insofar as we are reasonable, the simplest conceptual scheme into which the disorded fragments of raw experience can be fitted and arranged’.[83]

 

Our sense experiences must be organized; raw experience has to be arranged into a conceptual scheme.  Quine again employs the notion of a ‘conceptual scheme’ and the simpler the better.  Like Ockham, Quine sees no reason to violate the doctrine that entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem.  Unlike Ockham, Quine found no reason to ground meaning in some sort of universality. Quine wants to ground his ontological relativity in the physical sciences, yet his nominalistic view of reality does not leave room for physical entities.

 

 

 

PHENOMENALISM AND PHYSICALISM

 

 

Phenomenological conceptual schemes are epistemological, while physicalistic conceptual schemes (based in material-epiphenomenalism) are “physically fundamental”.[84] Phenomenological schemes do not claim to know substance, as it is noumenal or beyond appearance. All that can be known about the world is how it appears.  Physicalists do make a claim about substance, that it is material, or that causation all takes place within a material substance.  Hence phenomenalism and physicalism are contrary positions.  

 

            Quine spends little time discussing the phenomenalistic conceptual scheme. This epistemological dualist scheme admits a distinction between analytic statements, in which the predicate term is contained in the subject term, and the synthetic term, in which the predicate information cannot be known to apply to the subject without verification from sense experience. Examples of phenomenalistic conceptual schemes are found in the schemes of Hume and Kant.  Quine abandoned the analytic-synthetic distinction as well as challenged the concept of necessity.  He asks: “Which should prevail?” [85]  If we eliminate the analytic-synthetic distinction, then it is not yet clear which type of statements should prevail.  Should analytic statements prevail or should synthetic statements prevail?  Quine does not see how analytic propositions can be verified as true, and he thinks that only synthetic propositions have this quality.  Do they really?  It would appear that synthetic propositions or matters of fact, fall short of such verification. 

 

Quine says of the physicalistic conceptual scheme, since it claims to talk about external objects, that it “offers great advantages in simplifying our over-all reports.  By bringing together scattered sense events and treating them as perceptions of one object, we reduce the complexity of our stream of experience to a manageable conceptual simplicity.”[86]  This rule is a counter-Humean rule.  Hume wanted all simple ideas to be traced back to simple impressions as their source.[87]  Hume defines the distinction between impressions and idea in his A Treatise of Human Nature:

 

All the impressions of the human mind resolve themselves into two distinct kinds, which I shall call IMPRESSIONS and IDEAS.  The difference betwixt these consists in the degrees of force and liveliness, with which they strike upon the mind, and make their way into our thought and consciousness.  Those perceptions, which enter with most force and violence, we may call impressions; and under the name I comprehend all our sensations, passions, and emotions, as they make their first appearance in the soul.  By ideas I mean the faint images of these in thinking and reasoning; such as, for instance, all the perceptions excited by the present discourse, excepting only those which arise from the sight and touch and excepting the immediate pleasure or uneasiness it may occasion.[88]

 

Impressions and ideas can be divided into the simple and the complex.[89]  All simple ideas must be traced to simple impressions as their source.  Hume states this principle in his Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding:  "When we entertain, therefore, any suspicion that a philosophical term is employed without any meaning or idea (as is too frequent), we need but inquire, from what impressions is that supposed idea derived?" [90]  However, the bundles of perception inhibited the ability to find these simples, since a collection of experiences masks the individual impressions that led to the idea.  Quine seems to find these bundles simplifying, while Hume thought them to be the leveling of knowledge both of matters of fact and relations between ideas.  It seems unclear how conceptual schemes can be simplifying. Quine explains the rule of simplicity as:  “[O]ur guiding maxim in assigning sense data to objects:  we associate an earlier and later round of  sense datum with the so-called name penny, or with two different so-called pennies, in obedience to the demands of maximum simplicity in our total world picture” [91]  For the sake of simplicity, we assign names to sense data, and when we see objects which exhibit the standard named, we use same name for each.  It matters not if the penny in my pocket is not the same as the penny I had last weekend.  It is a penny none the less.

 

 

Of phenomenological and physicalistic conceptual schemes, both have advantages. He appreciated that phenomenalism only admits to knowing things as we believe them to be due to their appearances.  All that is known about reality is that which appears.  In phenomenalism, search for essence, and substance is not possible, since essential qualities and substance are hidden behind the veil of appearance. While using a phenomenalistic view, there was no need for Quine to commit to anything beyond appearance.   Quine later rejects the phenomenological view for the concrete objects of physicalism, as physics demands. The physical sciences deal with actual physical entities, and not just the mere appearance of those entities.  Most of the important entities of the physical sciences don't always appear to the unaided human eye.  Quine eventually finds an advantage in the physicalistic conceptual scheme because it brings together “scattered sense events” that are linked to “so-called” objects.[92]  Does it really? If the objects in question are too small, or elemental, Quine does not consider them to be concrete objects, although such objects are the bread and butter of the physical sciences.  Hence the advantage of the physical sciences seems to be diminished by Quine's limitation.

 

Quine, of course, is not optimistic that it is possible to convert

phenomenological conceptual schemes into physicalistic conceptual schemes.[93]  “Now what of classes or attributes of physical objects, in turn?”  Quine recognizes that for the phenomenologist, the physicalistic conceptual scheme is as much myth or superstition, as the phenomenological conceptual scheme is to physicalists. Can we know the attributes of objects via either schema?

           

            In his conclusion to “On What There Is,” Quine wants to see how far the reduction of a physicalistic conceptual scheme will fit into a phenomenalistic conceptual scheme.[94]  Quine wants to have mathematics free of Platonic myth, but at the same time inquires into its Platonic foundations.[95]  Quine claims that the phenomenalistic conceptual scheme is best able to handle the job, and it also takes what he calls “epistemological priority,” since it only claims to know objects as they appear and not the substance.[96]  Quine believed this because the phenomenological conceptual scheme is willing to admit that “ontologies of physical objects and mathematical objects are myths.”[97]  Myth has a relative quality. Each epistemological point of view is one among several points of view, each of which correspond to different interests and ends.[98] Hence Quine adopts and practices an ontological relativity.[99]  The question of “on what there is” does not refer to what there is in existence, but what we experience, and hence all we can know is about what there is.

 

.                Theories can take yet more drastic turns: such not merely to threaten a cherished ontology of elementary particles, but to threaten the very sense of the ontological question what there is.  What I have been taking as the standard idiom for existential purposes, namely quantification, can serve as a standard only when embedded in the standard form of regimented language that we have been     picturing: one whose apparatus consists only of truth functions and predicates.  If there is any deviation in this further apparatus, then there arises a questions of foreign exchange:  we cannot judge what existential content may be added by these foreign intrusions until we have settled on how to translate it all into our standard     form. [...]  A kindred notion may then stand forth that seems sufficiently akin to warrant application of the same word; such is the way of terminology.  Whether to say at that point that we have gained new insight into existence, or that we have outgrown the notion and reapplied the term, is a question of terminology as well.[100]

 

            Relativity is to be overcome by the use of a first order logical language.  If the terms can be defined and consent is established, then truth can be established within the system.  There could be quibbles over the meaning of words.  Without anything but our impressions of the world to guide defining, might there be difference in opinion over the meaning of terms, as in Through the Looking Glass?  However, mere quibbles over shades of meaning is not the true difficulty.  There are beliefs that cannot be translated into this logical syntax  Are such beliefs meaningless because they do not fit the system or is the system merely inadequate to account for such experience?  It is difficult to convert our sentiment and beliefs into a concrete logical syntax.[101]  There would be different kinds of beliefs for different believers, and such difference may be overlooked, or complicate understanding the meaning conveyed by the terms all together.  Quine contends that we do not have the ability to know if things exist, only our perceptions. The relativity of perceptions makes it difficult to understand what the terms truly mean.  Hence not only is Quine unable to know the things themselves, it seems that he is unable to explain the meaning of linguistic terms within a set web of beliefs.  This relativity is a result of a lack of universal understanding of the essential qualities that make a thing a certain kind of thing, and it is this essence that is being described by language.  Without acknowledgement of essential qualities which are a necessity to describe kinds of things, all descriptions, as well as things themselves, seem to be ambiguous.

 

Quine is willing to use a theory that has efficacy, and utility, and it seems that physicalism and nominalism are those theories.  It too seems that the claim of the physicalists that matter is real is a bit strong a position for a nominalist to take.  What the realists call “forms” are merely names according to nominalists.  Essence or form is essential (primary) substance or ousia.  Ousia is best defined as quid erat esse, or what it was to be.  Nominalism comes from the Latin word nominalis which means name, so nominalism is literally name-ism.  So what is real?  Most nominalists like to remain substance neutral, but Quine favors a type of physicalism in his later philosophy.

 

“Closeness of association with stimulation has stood up poorly as an argument for giving physical objects preferential status.  But something could still perhaps be salvaged from it.  For, grant that the question whether to dignify given words as terms is a question of what was said earlier for physical objects, viz. that terms for them are fairly directly associated with sensory stimulation, perhaps we could say this:  sentences fairly directly associated with sensory stimulation exhibit terms for physical objects in all sorts of term positions, not just in rather special positions.  It seems plausible that common terms for physical objects come out better by such a standard than abstract terms do.” [102]

  

Some do not even like to discuss matters of ontology in terms of existence of universal concepts like formal essences. The only existence nominalists will grant is the existence of particulars.  Today, talk of particulars has been changed to talk about objects.  Quine groups objects into kinds: “[i]n general we can take it as a very special mark of the maturity of a branch of science that it no longer needs an irreducible notion of similarity and kind.”[103]  However, the manner in which we identify these objects is not agreed upon by nominalists either.    

 

 

FOUR KINDS OF NOMINALISM:  PREDICATE, CONCEPT, CLASS, AND RESEMBLANCE

 

            Nominalism, in general, is the view that universals do not exist, but that only particulars exist.  All forms of nominalism share this basic premise.  Quine makes a major shift in his philosophy.  At first he criticizes nominalism, but in his later philosophy embraces the view.  Quine in fact is criticizing other forms of nominalism in favor of another.  Hence a discussion of the some of the main kinds of nominalism is essential to understanding Quine’s view.  The limitations of predicate, concept and class will be illustrated as to shed light upon why Quine favors resemblance nominalism.  Presently, Quine favors a nominalistic approach by holding the view that universals are not real, and do not have an existence what so ever.  Universals are only to be used as predicates.  He does not appear to favor the view here in “On What There is,” and in Word and Object makes a claim against nominalism. 

 

            Let a word therefore, have occurred as a fragment of ever so many empirically well-attested sentential wholes; even as a rather termlike fragment, by superficial appearances.  Still, the question whether to treat it as a term is the question whether to give it general access to positions appropriate to general  terms, or perhaps to singular terms, subject to the usual laws of such contexts. Whether to do so may reasonably be decided by considerations of systematic       efficacy, utility theory. But if nominalism and realism are to be adjudicated on such grounds, nominalism’s claims dwindle.  The reason for admitting numbers as objects is precisely their efficacy in organizing and expediting the sciences.  The reason for admitting to classes is much the same.[104]

 

All nominalists claim that what realists call universals are in fact merely names.  There are several forms of nominalism, including predicate nominalism, concept nominalism, class nominalism and resemblance nominalism. Nominalists think that the realists have gone to far in positing an existence of essences, or universals merely based on the word “is”.  This word is merely a copula, or linking verb, and in no way can imply the existence of something, since it is not a real predicate.[105]  The predicate adds no new information and predicates must predicate of something.  Kant uses this in his Critique of Pure Reason as a criticism of ontological arguments for the existence of God.  The word “is” added no new information than we had already had in the subject to begin with, hence “is” is not a real predicate. 

 

Ockham had one of the earliest criticisms of realists like Plato and Aristotle, although he was not the first nominalist.  Ockham denies that there could be some existence of essence separate from the individual that contains that essence.  Essences could not apply to more than one thing, since each thing is an individual or particular.

“In an individual, there is no universal nature really distinct from a contracting difference.  Such a nature could not be posited there unless it were an essential part of the individual itself.  But there is always a relation between whole and part such that, if the whole is singular and not common, then analogously each part in           the same way is singular.  For one part cannot be more singular than another.    Therefore, either no part of the individual is singular or every part of the individual is singular.  But not no part. Therefore every part. Likewise, if two such really   distinct factors were in the individual, does it not seem to involve a contradiction that one could be without the other.  In that case, the individual degree could be without the contracted nature or conversely, which is absurd.” [106]


If this is the case universals do not exist, only individuals. Every part of every individual is singular, or a particular, and in no way universal. Ockham is famous for his anti-realistic stance. He first called universals, ficta, or entities that only have intensional being.  Ockham later abandoned intensional being, and identified what realists call universals with the acts of understanding.[107]  All nominalists are not of the Ockham variety, and there are several forms of nominalism today.  Predicate nominalism, concept nominalism, class nominalism, and resemblance nominalism are all forms of nominalism discussed in this section.  All forms of nominalism have a fundamental belief that universals do not exist, but are merely names. 

 

The first form of nominalism to be discussed is predicate nominalism.

Predicate nomimalists, link general terms, predicates, to the subjects to which they apply.  These predications are not universals, but merely names or qualities or attributes of a subject.  The predicate is said to be true of the particular, but philosophers like Armstrong think this to be misleading, since the predicate nominalist has not verified this using an objective process.  How can we be certain that these predicates are in fact true of the particular we apply it to?[108]  Since there can be many interpretations of the sense fields of empirical experience via which empirical nominalists gain their knowledge of the world, it is impossible to even objectively know the world as it is.  The predicate nominalists use a method of analysis like:  A has property F if and only if a falls under the predication F”.[109]  But since there is no way to verify this application empirically (a posteriori) or rationally (a priori), how can we be so certain?  This does not eliminates nominalism, since predicate nominalism is only one type.

 

            The second form of nominalism is concept nominalism.  Concept nominalism is a lot like conceptualism, in that these nominalists  use concepts. This is very much like the predicate nominalism just discussed.  They even use the same method of analysis as the predicate nominalists: “A has property F if and only if a falls under the predication F”.[110]  Armstrong goes on to state that since predicate and concept nominalisms are so close in relation, one criticism could be used to attack both effectively.  The problem is with the concepts used as predicates.  What is whiteness?  Can one definition suffice?  Can we employ an axiom that all things similar to this thing is a white thing?  What does white mean?  This is an infinite regress much like the one posed by Plato’s separation of matter from form.  Will the term be applied by all individuals universally in the same way? An empiricist may be tempted to show whiteness to another to prove its meaning -- but what allows the empiricist to bracket a determination of whiteness at that time?  Can that bracketing apply to all situations of whiteness?  It is hardly likely. And furthermore, can predicates be taken to be real properties? It does not seem possible that such concepts can be accurate predications of real particulars since, as it has been said before, there are no objective means to verify predication using empirical means absent universal essences.

           

            Class nominalism is a third type of nominalism which attempts to class group particulars into categories of similarity.  Many, like Quine, consider this type of nominalism to be self-contradictory.[111]  If we have really abandoned Plato and his realism then what are we using abstract entities for anyway? Armstrong dismisses Quine’s criticism, and includes class nominalism as a real type of nominalism.  Class nominalists use this method of analysis:  A has property, F, if and only if A is a member of the class of F’s.”[112]  The problem arises in class nominalism in a case where classes are identical only if they have identical members, such as F and G, which have identical members.  But this violates the rule given to us by the class nominalists, since the class of F is identical to the class of G.  This is even more problematic if F and G are empty sets, and hence refer to the same (non) set of entities.[113]  F and G would have every property, identically, and hence why make a distinction between F’s and G’s in the first place? What does it really mean to “be a member of” a class?

            What makes ontological questions meaningless when taken absolutely is not universality but circularity.  A question of the form “What is an F?” can be answered only by recourse to a further term:  “An F is a G.”  The answer makes only relative sense:  sense relative to the uncritical acceptance of “G”.[114]

 

Quine acknowledges that there is no way to answer the dilemma of the third man - what is a G?  He thinks that it must be uncritically accepted since “G” is without possible definition.  “All G’s are X”.  “What is an X?” is the next question.  These are circular definitions and it is never clear what G is. Leibniz, in his Monadology was well aware of this difficulty and came up with his principle of indiscernibles.  “For there are never in nature two beings which are exactly alike, and in which it is not possible to find a difference either internal or based on intrinsic property.”[115]  There must be a difference between every G and every X or there would not be the distinction  of G-ness and X-ness perceived in the first place.[116]

           

            Resemblance nominalism is the fourth type of nominalism to be discussed in this paper.  The type of analysis used is this:  A has the property F, if and only if A suitably resembles a paradigm case (or paradigm cases) of an F.”[117]  Quine calls such test cases “foils”.

 

            Without serious loss of accuracy we can assume that there are one or more actual things (paradigm cases) that nicely exemplify the desired norm, and one or more actual things (foils) that deviate just barely too much to be counted into the desired kind at all, then our definition is easy:  the kind with paradigm a and foil b is the set of all the things to with a is more similar than a is to b.  More generally, then a set may be said to be a kind if and only if there are a and b, known or unknown, such that the set is the kind with paradigm a and foil b[118]

 

So, if we can compare the particular to its other kinds, then we can fit it into a group of others which resemble it.  Quine claims we learn how to make this fit by ostension .[119] Hume states of resemblance:  “that every passion, which that idea occasions, whether of joy or sorrow, acquires new force and vigor.”[120]   We will learn how to fit the members into groups to which they resemble, by trial and error,

 

            Quine uses a mixture of verification and falsification, but the foil, too, needs to be verified as being the foil.  Armstrong thinks that finding truth by trial and error is more of a statement of the problem of nominalism rather than a solution.[121]  Resemblance nominalism is no better than class nominalism, and in fact it contains all the same difficulties.  What does resemblance really mean?  How far can we apply the resemblance?  Cannot all particulars resemble all others in that they are all particulars?  This is not very informative.  White cannot, according to Armstrong, be an essence like a Platonic form, nor is it just a mental concept.[122]

 

Nominalists do not pretend to know anything beyond the particulars or objects they observe.  But because of the relativity of sense data, and the lack of an absolute interpretation of sensations, it is not clear how a nominalist like Quine can know particulars at all.  Most empiricists admit that all that is knowable is these perceptions and not that which the perceptions are about, the objects in and of themselves.  It is due to Quine’s view of resemblance nominalism that he seeks to favor the phenomenalistic conceptual scheme in the end of “On What There Is.”[123]  He does this, because, in order to check our logical claims, to determine the extents to which bound variables apply, the nominialistic view is that what can be bound by a variable, must be rooted in the qualities of the objects being observed.  How else can we know things except by way of “raw experience”?[124]  That is all that is real, according to Quine -- objects. He resorts to physicalism over phenomenalism.[125]  Using the principle of simplicity, the actual qualities of the actual objects could be quantified by bound variables. Such a principle relies on the notion of synonymy.  Quine cannot demonstrate that he knows the things in the world are as they are, and hence his use of sense fields and ontological relativity makes it impossible to know that by which variables are bound.

 

            At first Quine seems to be a phenomenalist, holding the position in his earliest years, that things cannot be know themselves.  Only the appearances seem to be knowable.  This fits Quine’s early view of nominalism, especially his resemblance nominalism.  Things are kinds of the same type if they are more like each other than they differ.  Phenomenalism was selected rather than physicalism, it seems, since physicalism does make a claim about things as they really are.  Things are physical, or made out of matter.  Typically matter is seen a substance.  Some claim that even the physical is a mere appearance, and thus there is not a conflict between phenomenalism, and physicalism.  I beg to differ.  It must be the case that there are fundamental differences between the two positions, otherwise they would be distinctions without a difference.  There is a major distinction between phenomenalism and physicalism:  the distinction is that phenomenal does not pretend to know that which transcends appearance, while physicalism does.  The physical existence of things is not mere appearance, but a quality that goes beyond appearance.  The basic building blocks of matter, subatomic particles, are beyond appearance when using only the human eye, yet we know they exist by other means, such as electron microscopes. There exists something beyond the mere appearance of things. 

 

Quine does not abandon his nominalistic position when he makes his shift to physicalism in his later philosophy.  This seems very inconsistent.  Nominalism claims that things are merely names, and not universals, and not physical entities.  It is imporant to recognize this contrast in his early and later views regarding ontology.  Where before he was not going to favor either physicalism, nor conceptualism or realism, language and sense experience were interconnected and could not be independent of one another.  We had no more understanding about one or the other.   



 

[15]             “On What There Is,” W.V.O. Quine, From A Logical Point Of View, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 15

 

[16]             Ibid., 19.

 

[17]              Ibid., 1.

 

[18]             Ibid.  Jaakko Hintikka remarks of this response given by Quine, that ‘everything’ is a response only an universalist can give.  “For a universalist, there is only one range for one’s (first order) quantifiers, viz., all the individual objects in the world.  It is for such reasons that Quine has been concerned with the unification of universes even in his technical logical theory and has argued that there is basically only one sense of existence.” Jaakko Hintikka,  Quine As A Member Of The Tradition” as in Perspectives on Quine,  Robert Barrett and Roger Gibson, editors, (Oxford:  Blackwell, 1993), page 164.

 

[19]             Ibid.

 

[20]             Ibid.

 

[21]             Ibid., 2.

 

[22]             Ibid., 3.

 

 

[23]             Immanual Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, translated by JMD Meiklejohn, (Buffalo, NY:  Prometheus Books, 1990), 335. “Now if I take the subject (God) with all the predications (omnipotence being one), and say, God is, or, There is a God, I add no new predicate to the conception of God, I merely posit or affirm the existence of the subject with all its predications-- I posit the object in relation to my conception.  The content of both is the same; and there is no addition made to the conception, which expresses merely the possibility of the object, by my cogitating the object-- in the expression, it is-- as absolutely given or existing.  Thus the real contains no more than the possible. A hundred real dollars contain no more than a hundred possible dollars.”

 

[24]             Ibid., 5.  Bertrand Russell, Logic and Knowledge, (New York, NY:  Routledge, 1994), 51. Russell defines his singular-descriptions:  “Thus if ‘C’ is a denoting phrase, it may happen that there is one entity x (there cannot be more than one) for which the proposition ‘x is identical with C’ is true, this proposition being interpreted as above.  We may then say that the entity x is the denotation of the pharse ‘C’.”

 

[25]             Ibid., 6-7.

 

 

[26]             Ibid., 7.

 

[27]             Ibid.

 

[28]             Ibid.

 

[29]             Ibid.  I think that Quine employs the use of Russell’s theory of descriptions.  There is considerable controversy over the theory of descriptions.   Strawson agrees with me, and also notes that singular-descriptions will in effect eliminate singular terms.  Peter Strawson, Individuals, (New York, NY:  Routledge, 1990), 195.

 

                Russell uses the theory of types, which refers to classes, to escape the paradox.  The problem is that some classes are members of themselves.  This results in a contradiction.  Is R a member of itself?  If it is a member of itself it belongs to the class of all classes that are members of themselves.  If it is not a member of itself it belongs to the class of all classes that are not members of themselves.  So either way, it still is a member of itself.  To remedy this problem, Russell describes his theory for a gradation of types, in his essay “Mathematical Logic as Based on a Theory of Types.”  “‘Whatever contains an apparent variable must not be a possible value of that variable.’ Thus whatever contains an apparent variable must be of a different type from the possilbe values of that variable; we will say that it is of a higher type.  Thus the apparent variables contained in an expression are what determines its type. [...] The terms of elementary propositions we will call individuals; these form the first level or lowest type. [...] Elementary propositions together with such as contain only individuals as apparent variables we will call first-order propositions.  These form the second logical type. We thus have a new totality, that of first-order propositions.  We can thus form new propositons in which first-order propositions occur as apparent variables.  These we will call second-order propositions; these form the third logical type.”  Logic and Knowledge, 75-76.

 

                Russell defines the difference between description and acquaintance in his Problems of Philosophy.  Bertrand Russell, Problems of Philosophy, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), page 46.  “Knowledge of things by description, always involves, [...] some knowledge of truths as its source or ground.”  On the other hand knowledge of things by acquaintance does not require knowing any such

truths.  He goes on to define acquaintance as “anything of which we are directly aware without the intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truths.”  To describe a table is to note certain truths about tables. 

 

[30]         W.V.O. Quine, Word and Object, (Cambridge, MA:  The MIT Press, 1960), section 13:  “Translation and Meaning,” 56. In section 12, 53 Quine states:  “We cannot even say what native locutions to count as analogues of terms as we know them, much less equate them with ours term for term, except as we have also decided what native devices to view as doing in their various ways the work of our own various auxiliaries to objective reference:  our articles and pronouns, our singular and plural, our copula, our identity predicate.”  In section 20, “Predication” Quine goes on to explain that terms like ‘Pegasus’ are learned by description.  (page 95).

 

[31]             Ibid., 8.

 

[32]             Ibid.

 

 

[33]             Ibid., 3.

 

[34]             Ibid., 9.

 

[35]             Ibid., 10.

 

[36]          “Word and Object,” 3.  Quine discusses conceptual schemes in “Word and Object.”  “There is every reason to inquire into the sensory or stimulatory background of ordinary talk of physical things. This mistake comes only in seeking an implicit sub-basement of conceptualization, or of language.  Conceptualization on any considerable scale is inseparable from language, and our ordinary language of physical things is about as basic as language gets.” 

 

[37]             “On What There Is,” 10.

 

 

[38]             W.V.O. Quine, From A Logical Point Of View, (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1980), 79.

 

[39]             Ibid.

 

[40]             Of this Orestein remarks:  “Thus, singular existentials such as ‘Quine exists’, were said to be meaningless because the string ‘($x) Quine’ is not well formed.  Fortunately fashions have changed.  Strawson has reminded us how much names are like descriptions (Strawson 1963).”  Alex Orestein,  Is Existence...?” as in Perspectives on Quine, Robert Barrett and Roger Gibson, editors,  (Oxford:  Blackwell, 1993), 266.

 

 

[41]             “On What There Is,  9.  Quine contends that it is a moot point.  Quine is not concerned with proving that his definition of meaning is correct, but in showing how those that accept the existence of universals have misunderstood the difference between meaning and naming.  Named objects are not merely conceptual.  Accordingly, meanings are not, on their own, evidence for the existence of a namable (actual) entities.

 

[42]             Ibid.  Kripke agrees with Quine on this point, and thinks that such truths are contingent, and not necessary.  “But neither of those are necessary truths even if that’s the way we pick out the planet.  These are the contingent marks by which we identify a certain planet and give it a name.” Saul A. Kripke, Naming and Necessity, (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1980), 105.

 

[43]             From A Logical Point Of View, 139 -159. Intensional objects can be quantified over by bound variables, if they are analytically equivalent.  Quine rejects the notion of analyticity in his “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.”  An analytical judgment is a judgment in which the predicate term contains no more information than the subject term.  The predicate is synonymous with the subject. 

 

[44]             “On What There Is,” 11.  In “Word and Object,  Quine explains about intension:  “One may accept the Brentano thesis either as showing the indispensability of intensional idioms and the importance of an autonomous science of intention, or as showing the baselessness of intentional idioms and the emptiness of a science of intention.  My attitude, unlike Brentano’s, is the second.  To accept intentional usage at face value is, we say, to postulate translation relations as somehow objectively valid though indeterminate in principle relative to the totality of speech dispositions.” 221.  Quine is not interested in connotation, but denotation.  Quine prefers ‘is true of’ to the usage of ‘denoting’.  Sometimes extensional meaning is described as denoting, while intensional meaning is described as connotation. Quine explains:  “The phrase ‘is true of’ is less open to misunderstanding;  clearly ‘wicked’ is not true of the quality of wickedness, nor the class of wicked persons, but of each wicked person individually.”  W.V. Quine, Methods of Logic, Fourth Edition, (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1982), 94.

 

[45]             “On What There Is,” 12.

 

 

[46]             Word and Object, 191.

 

[47]             Naming and Necessity, 27.  “Frege specifically said that such a description gave the sense of the name.”  Names that do not stand for descriptions don’t have any sense.

 

[48]             “On What There Is,” 12.

 

[49]             Ibid., 13.

 

[50]             Ibid., 15

 

 

[51]             Daniel Bonevac, Simple Logic, (Fort Worth, TX:  Harcourt Brace, 1999), 344.

 

[52]             “On What There Is,  13.  He adds, “nouns might have been named propronouns.”

 

[53]             Ibid.

 

[54]             Ibid., 13-14.

 

[55]             Ibid.

 

[56]             Ibid., 14.

 

[57]             Ibid., 14-15.

 

 

[58]             Ibid., 14.  “Realism [is the view] (in scholastic philosophy [...] contrasted with nominalism) that universals have a real and substantial existence, independently of being thought. [...] Most commonly the view (contrasted with idealism) that physical objects exist independently of being perceived.  Thus understood, realism obviously reaffirms the standpoint of common sense.”

 

[59]             Antony Flew,editior, A Dictionary of Philosophy, (New York:  St. Martin’s Press, 1984),  299.

 

[60]             “On What There Is,” 14.

 

[61]             A Dictionary of Philosophy,  215.  But arithmetic was lowered to the realm of set theory.

 

[62]             “On What There Is,  2.

 

[63]             A Dictionary of Philosophy,  250.

 

[64]             “On What There Is,  5.  “I have spoken disparagingly of Plato’s beard, and hinted that it is tangled.”  And it is this “inconvenience” of  putting” up with Plato’s theory that led Quine to develop his own ontology.

 

[65]             Ibid., 14.

 

[66]              Ibid.

 

[67]             A Dictionary of Philosophy, 69.

 

[68]             W. V. Quine, Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, Revised Edition, (Cambridge:  University of Harvard Press, 1976), “On Mental Entities,” 221.

 

[69]             Ibid.

 

[70]             A Dictionary of Philosophy, 178.

 

[71]             “On What There Is,” 14.

 

[72]             Ibid., 15.

 

[73]             Ibid.

 

[74]             Ibid.

 

[75]             Ibid.

 

[76]             W.V. Quine and J.S. Ullian, The Web of Belief, Second Edition, (New York:  McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1970), 76.

 

[77]              Ibid.

 

[78]             Ibid.  Hence Quine is not concerned with quid erat esse, but merely about what there is. 

 

[79]             Ibid.

 

[80]             Ibid., 16.

 

[81]             Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland & Through the Looking-Glass, (New York:  Bantam Classic, 1988), 168-169.

 

[82]             Ibid.

 

 

[83]             “On What There Is,  16.

 

[84]             Ibid.

 

[85]             Ibid.

 

[86]             Ibid., 17.

 

 

[87]             Hume, “A Treatise of Human Nature,” in Philosophers Speak for Themselves:  Berkeley, Hume, and Kant, edited by T.V. Smith and Marjorie Grene, (Chicago, IL:  University of Chicago Press, 1957), 106-107.

 

[88]             Ibid. Hume also defines these terms in his Enquires Concerning Human Understanding (Book 1, section 2, 12.)

 

[89]             “[...] I must make use of the distinction, of perceptions into simple and complex, to limit this general decision, that all our ideas and impressions are resembling.  I observe, that many of our complex ideas never had impressions, that corresponded to them, and many of our complex impressions are never exactly copied into ideas.” “Treatise,” 108.

 

[90]             David Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, revised third edition,  P. H. Nidditch (Oxford:  Oxford University Press, 1995), 22.

 

[91]             “On What There Is,  17. Quine explains the rule of simplicity as:  “[O]ur guiding maxim in assigning sense data to objects:  we associate an earlier and later round of  sense datum with the so-called name penny, or with two different so-called pennies, in obedience to the demands of maximum simplicity in our total world picture”

 

[92]             Ibid.

 

[93]             Ibid., 18.

 

[94]             Ibid., 19.

 

[95]             Ibid.

 

[96]             Ibid.       

 

[97]             Ibid.

 

[98]             Ibid.

 

[99]             W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and other essays, (New York:  Columbia University Press, 1969), 138.

 

[100]            W.V.O. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1990), 35-36.

 

[101]            Wittgenstein comments in Philosophical Grammar, that there is nothing to be gained by using the Russellian notation $x.  “Ordinary language says “In this square there is a red circle”; the Russellian notation says “There is an object which is red circle in this square.” [...] Perhaps even the expression “there is” is misleading.”  page 267.  Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar, edited by Rush Rhees, (Berkeley:  University of California Press),  266-267.

 

[102]             Word and Object,  237-238.

 

[103]            “Natural Kinds,  138. See Metaphysics  1015 a.  “Nature is styled the substance of things that exist by Nature;  [...]  metaphorically speaking and generally, every substance is called Nature, also is a certain substance.”  Naming and Necessity,  127. Kripke defines natural kinds as being like proper names, and applies this view to mass terms such as gold and water.

 

[104]            Word and Object,  236-237.

 

[105]            Bertrand Russell,  The Existential Import of Propositions,” The Collected Dialogues, Volume 4:  Foundations of Logic 1903-1905.  (New York:  Routledge, 1994).

 

 

[106]            William of Ockham “Five Questions on Universals  Paul Vincent Spade (translator and editor), Five Texts on the Medieval Problem of Universals, (Indianapolis, IN:  Hackett Publishing Company, 1994), 152.

 

[107]            Dictionary, 374.

 

[108]            D. M. Armstrong, Nominalism and Realism, Universals and Scientific Realism, Vol. 1, (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 1978), 13.

 

[109]            Ibid. 

 

[110]            Ibid. 

 

[111]            Ibid.  Quine believes that:  “[t]hey [set theorists] treat of no distinctive objects and indiscriminately of all.”  Methods of Logic,  fourth edition,  302.

 

[112]            Ibid.

 

[113]            Armstrong,  35-36.

 

[114]             “Ontological Relativity,” 153.

 

[115]            G. W. Leibniz, Monadology, (Lasalle, IL:  Open Court Classics, 1995), 252. (#9).

 

[116]            Donald Davidson and J. Hintikka, Word and Objections:  Essays on the Work of W. V. Quine, (Boston:  D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1975), 260.  Berry’s essay “Logic With Platonism” explains the “Platonistic interpretations of G.G here is ‘the best grand logic.’  Berry asks:  “How then do we find out about this realm of extra-mental, non-particular, unobservable entities?  Our knowledge of them, like our knowledge of the extra-mental, unobservable objects of the physical sciences, is indirect, being tied to perceived things by a fragile web of theory.”

 

[117]            Armstrong , 15.

 

[118]            Ontological Relativity and other essays,  121. 

 

[119]            Ibid.

 

[120]            Enquiries, 51.

 

[121]            Armstrong, 44.

 

[122]            Armstrong,  44.

 

 

[123]            Quine notes how the formalistic mathematical scheme was the one to which he subscribed in  "On What There Is," 18.   The discovery of Russell’s paradox and other contradictions arose in set theory and became a challenge to Quine and his resemblance nominalism, and he notes how “[t]hese contradictions had to be obviated by unintuitive, ad hoc devices; our mathematical myth making became deliberate and evident to all.” So, Quine, a nominalist was not free from myth as he admits, since he adopted the myths of mathematics and physics. 

 

[124]            “On What There Is,  14.

 

[125]            Perspectives on Quine, 322.  Quine’s view is described as a kind of physicalism and epiphenomenalism by Barry Stroud in his essay “Quine’s Physicalism.”  The use of proxy functions will ensure that the dualistic dilemma of the separation of mind and the physical [solipsism] is avoided.  Stoud also describes Quine’s sense field theory on page 323.